“The soul doubtless is immortal
Where a soul can be discerned.”
Browning: A Toccata of Gallupi’s
What is a punk? In Shakespeare’s day, it meant a
prostitute. But an Elizabethan who had
invented a time machine and who asked for a punk in 1980’s London might have
been startled by the result.
What, then, is the
difference between a gift and a talent?
Although both concepts have their origins in the Bible, answers to this
question can vary widely: depending on whether they are rooted in a religious
or in a secular understanding of the terms.
In
a Biblical context, gifts are the province only of believers. They are given by the Spirit at conversion,
or at some point afterwards, with the purpose of building up the Church that is
the body of Christ in the world. They
are complementary, to enable the metaphorical body to function. Some believers may have more than one gift,
but every believer has at least one.
They do not necessarily mean spectacular ability or intelligence, but
each gift is a way of furthering God’s purpose.
Gifts
are dealt with in Paul’s letters; talents crop up in two linked parables, in
which they are sums of money. In
Matthew’s version, one servant is given five talents, another is given two, and
a third only one. It is not made clear whether or not there were other servants
who were not given any at all. In Luke’s
version, ten servants – it seems to suggest all the servants within the household
– are given one mina (part of a talent) each.
If
from Matthew’s version we try to define talents as special donations given only
to a few, and distributed unequally, then Luke’s version seems to suggest just
the opposite. The common message in
both, however, is using what you have been given. If you have a talent, or talents, you will
be accountable to God for the use you have made of it or them: whether you
believe in God or not.
Religious terms are no
more exempt than any others from the processes of semantic change. In Matthew,
the amount given to each servant is “according to his ability.” Over time, the sum of money and the ability
the sum represents have merged with each other; so that ‘talent’ has come to
mean the innate aptitude itself. So do
we say that anyone can have a talent, but only a believer can have a gift?
‘Gift’, however, has
also changed its meaning. How can there by a gift of the Spirit if you no
longer believe in the Spirit; and Nature, rather than God, is the source of everything? What seems to remain of the concept in
popular thought is the idea that everyone is given a gift by Nature.
That probably underlies
the conviction found in some that you can do anything if you want to hard
enough: what matters is the degree of intent, not the level of innate
ability. “Where there’s a will there’s a
way.” Or the, “Where there’s a Will
there’s a way of Behaviourism.” Above a
certain level of intelligence, anyone can be turned into anything. Shakespeare, with appropriate tweaking, could
have been an Einstein. This is in
striking contrast to St Paul’s
view of the Body: in which an eye is an eye, and can’t be turned into an ear
with a bit of retraining. It’s also,
incidentally, contrary to the view of J K Rowling’s Mr Ollivander: “The wand chooses the wizard, Mr Potter. The wizard doesn’t choose the wand.”
Modern educational theory reflects
a developed, secularized understanding of these old religious concepts. Educational theory, ever since computers
enabled us to compile international league tables of performance and we can
compare the performance of our children with those of Norway or Malaysia, has been much exercised
by the issue of the gifted and talented.
On the other hand, educational theory – commendably enough – is also
much given to inclusion. It’s like
trying to square Matthew’s version of the parable with Luke’s. The gifted and talented suggest exclusivity,
whereas inclusion means leaving nobody out.
It’s a conundrum. The result is
usually some sort of inclusive gifted and talented, and behind it is probably
the belief that a talent is the province of the few and a gift is the
entitlement of everybody...
Actually, defining
educational theory’s understanding of the difference between a gift and a
talent is no mean feat. When you look at
various mission statements, the focus seems to be on justifying how the gifted
and talented differ from the rest of us, rather than on how the two words
differ from one another. It’s a bit like
trying to pin down the distinction between form and structure, or cleverness
and intelligence. One is tempted to
dismiss it as yet another example of Education’s love of tautology. Otherwise, it’s a variation of meaning so
fine that only the gifted and/or talented are able to understand what it
is.
If you persist,
however, you can find out that, in modern educational terms, ‘a gift’ means
theoretical intelligence, and ‘a talent’ means practical intelligence. That is, you’d be gifted if you were a
composer, but talented if you were a performer; and gifted and talented if you
were both. Shakespeare, being both
dramatist and actor, would have been both gifted and talented.
Confined to education, these new
secular definitions seem to me to work well.
It is when they are directed back at the Christianity that gave rise to
them – when we speak of Christ as “a moral genius” or of someone as having “a
talent for religion” – that difficulties occur.
Or so they seem to me. What is
absolutely key in each case is to decide what is the province of the few, and
what is the entitlement of everybody.
What
is ‘a moral genius’? (I am treating
‘genius’ here as someone who is unusually gifted). Asked to define it as it stands, I would say
it means an unusually gifted person who behaves in a moral way: as opposed to
the many geniuses who have been spectacularly immoral in their behaviour.
That,
of course, is not at all what those who use the term understand by it. As far as I can see, they mean someone who is
able to invent a new moral system, as a composer might ‘invent’ a new
symphony.
Is having a moral sense
a gift like having a gift for music – some people can compose a new melody,
most can’t: and those who can have the choice of whether or not to do so – or
is morality more like the gift of the breath of life? If you choose not to breathe, you die; and at
some stage even that choice is taken from you.
What I’m getting at, of
course, is rival theories about the origin of conscience. In The
Book of Jeremiah, God says, “I will write my law in their hearts.” Conscience is innate: people have got it,
even if – like air conditioning in a modern car – they choose not to use
it.
Against this is the
theory that ‘conscience’ is simply a variant of the superego: formed by the prevailing value system of
whatever society you happen to grow up in.
These two incompatibles lead in very different directions. Think of the
difference between a Nazi feeling guilty about sending Jews to be gassed
(innate conscience), or feeling guilty about not sending Jews to be gassed (social conscience).
The best examples I
know of this sort of thing are in Huckleberry
Finn. Huck is constantly guilty that
he is helping Jim, the runaway slave, to escape, so that Jim can be reunited
with his family and achieve freedom.
Huck never seems to think about Jim’s children, although Jim does. His focus is on having wronged Miss Watson,
Jim’s owner.
In one scene, Jim is
mourning because he thinks Huck is dead.
Really, Huck has simply been hiding for fun. When Jim learns the truth, he turns his back
in hurt. Eventually, Huck
apologises. He realises how wrong he has
been to do so, but is defiantly glad that he has done it, whatever people
think. There, in essence, is the
difference between the two systems: the ‘conscience’ of the racist South, and
the real-life consciousness of having wronged another human being. Everything about Huck’s upbringing and
parental example militates against such a consciousness being there.
What then about ‘a talent for religion’? In the eyes of those who would use such a
term, ‘religion’ is probably nothing more than the system of ethics that holds
a particular culture together; in which case, a talent for religion probably
means not much more than being a good listener.
Is religion something
that some people have a talent for, as they might have a talent for playing
hockey? That must depend on whether
religion is a human invention, or a transcendent reality. If it’s the former, then religion is like
belonging to some minority film club, if you happen to like that sort of thing
and can appreciate the sort of stuff that’s boring or baffling to the average
viewer. If it’s the latter, then it’s
more like council tax, or the rules of the road; you are implicated whether you
want to be or not.
What alarms me about “a
talent for religion” is where it has taken us in the past, and where it might take
us in the future. Either that no one has
a soul, or that only some of us have: views that, respectively, could lead us
to a new Gulag, or to a new Auschwitz.
No comments:
Post a Comment